際際滷

際際滷Share a Scribd company logo
Diego Gabriel Krivochen (UNLP, Universit辰t Potsdam)
Previous approaches
Pesetsky & Torrego (2001, 2004, 2007)

 Vehicle Requirement on Merge (2007: 1):
If 留 and 硫 merge, some feature F of 留 must probe F on 硫.

 Conditions for Probing:
C-command
Feature identity
A model of Agree
 Agree (Feature sharing version)
i)   An unvalued feature F (a probe) on a head H at
     syntactic location 留 (F留) scans its c-command
     domain for another instance of F (a goal) at location
     硫 (F硫) with which to agree.

ii) Replace F留 with F硫, so that the same feature is
     present in both locations.
Problems
 C-command is stipulatively defined upon 2-D tree-like
  representations.
 Restrictions on Merge: the operation does not follow
  from conceptual necessity but from intra-theoretical
  needs.
 Substantive complications: features, values, operations
  (Agree = Search + Copy Value)
Case in P&Ts model
 Relation between Case in NPs and T finiteness (P&T,
 2000: 5):

The nature of nominative case
Nominative case is uT on D.

uT on D is valued by non-defective T

The concept is extended to ACC case, depending on the
 T node that values the uninterpretable feature on D.
Case as a subtype of Agree
 NOM = [TS [u-]DP[u-T]]



 ACC = [TO [u-] DP [u-T]]
Case in Radical Minimalism
 Case is a configurational relation, not a substantive
  element (Cf. P&T, Chomsky)

 Relation between Theta-Theory and Case Theory:


 The optimal scenario would be that in which there is
  a univoque relation between theta positions and
  theta roles, and a Case interpretation for each
  theta-position.
DeLancey (2001)
 () suppose we could demonstrate that there are, say,
 exactly x universal semantic roles which can occur as
 core arguments in a clause in human language. The
 most obvious language design would have x case
 markers, one for each underlying role; every
 argument would simply be marked for its semantic
 role, which could then be read directly off the
 surface morphosyntax () (our highlighting)
vP


慮1         v


 [CAUSE]        VP


      [GO/BE]        PP


                慮2        P


               [WITH] / [TO]   慮3
 Initiator will be assigned to the position 慮1,
  Theme (for Figure) and Location (for Ground)
  vary between 慮2 and 慮3 depending on the
  nature of the P head, central or terminal
  coincidence. If P is central, then the Ground
  will 慮2 and 慮3, Figure, while if P is terminal, it
  will be the other way around.
 Force is within the Initiator sphere
  Percept ("perceived entity") in the area
  of Theme
  Source, Path, Goal, Experiencer (see De Lancey,
  2001), are interpreted within the Location
  sphere.
 Case is the result of the local relationship between an
  argument and a functional-procedural node.
 We will work with a system of three cases, also structured
  as "spheres", in close relation to thematic roles. These
  underlying and universal cases would be Nominative,
  Accusative and Dative, names that we maintain as a matter
  of convenience and expository purposes, but we really
  should talk about an Initiator Case (Agent / Force), a
  Theme Case and a Location Case (comprising variants of
  terminal / central coincidence), regardless possibilities of
  morphological realization in different languages.

  Nominative - Initiator
   Accusative - Theme
   Dative - Location
 Nominative: read off from a {Time, {D}} local relation,
  and interpreted thematically (in the explicature
  building process, see Sperber & Wilson, 2003) as Agent
  / Force

 Accusative: read off from a {Cause, {D}} local relation,
  and interpreted thematically as Theme, the object
  (Figure) located in / moving towards, etc. a Ground

 Dative: read off from a {P, {D}} local relation, and
  interpreted thematically as Location, the Ground in
  Talmys terms.
An essential claim is that the spheres are not 束far apart損, but in
interaction, and there are points of contact. There are elements,
uses of the VI corresponding canonically to one 束Case損 that
appear in unusual configurations: of these, we will say they are
束intersective uses損 of the Cases (blue circles):


                             NOM




                     ACC              DAT
Examples:
Accusative > Dative: ACC expresses location in space, time
  or property (i, ii and iii), or goal in movement (iv).
 Direction Accusative:
Latin: Eo RomamACC (Lit. Go Rome I go towards/to Rome)
Sanskrit: grmamACC gacchami (Lit. Town go I go to the
  town)
Polish: id na pocztACC I am going to the post office, id添 po
  niegoACC go for him (go to pick him up)
 Temporal Accusative:
Latin: quamdiu, quamdudum, quanto tempore complements.
≒Double accusative in ditransitive constructions: traditionally
referred to as thing ACC and person ACC, they are within the
P domain, as Theme and Goal.

Latin: Verres MilesiosACC navemACC poposcit. (Lit. Verres the
milesians ship asked Verres asked a ship to the milesians),
Quid meACC istudACC rogas? (Lit. Why to-me this ask? Why do
you ask me this?)
Greek: 隆旅隆略虜 凌 留樽隆留 流僚 粒留亮亮留旅虜流僚 [did叩sk to炭s
pa樽dasACC t畍n grammatik畍nACC] (Lit. I teach to-the children
grammar I teach grammar to the children)
Sanskrit: rjnamACC vacanamACC abrav朝t (Lit. King some words
said (He/She) said some words to the king)
Accusative > Nominative: ACC is the overt subject in non-finite clauses.

ECM (Exceptional Case Marking):
Ingl辿s: I want [themACC to come]
Lat鱈n: Video [teACC venire] (Lit. See you to-come, I see you coming)
Griego: 了劉粒竜旅 竜 畆了慮竜樽僚 [l辿gei [seACC elthe樽nINF]] (Lit. dice te haber venido active
aorist infinitive- (He/She) says you have come)
Polish: Widz ciACC spicego. (I see you sleeping.)

Dative > Nominative: Dative appears in subject position in the Spelled-Out
form.

Quirky case:
Icelandic: HenniDAT leiddust 聾 NOM (Lit. Her bored they They bored her)
                              eir
     MerDAT 聾 [MariaNOM vera garfu] (Lit. To me seems Mary be intelligent
              坦tti
Mary seems to me to be intelligent)
Polish: MariiNOM znudzia si pracaNOM. (Mary got bored with work)
         JanowiDAT podoba si we Woszech. (John likes it in Italy.)
Spanish: A JuanDAT leDAT basta con eso. (cf. Fernandez Soriano, 1999)
         A Mar鱈aDAT leDAT gusta el jazz
Values of the Genitive (DAT Sphere)
 Posession (material or metaphorical):
Sanskrit: Damayantys svaya畊baras (Lit. Damayantis choice)
Latin: id est domusNOM regisGEN (Lit. This is house of the king This is the house
  of the king)
Greek: 畆 凌畆偉採留 凌短 留 [h oik鱈a to短 patr坦sGEN] (Lit. The house of the father)
Polish: sprawaNOM MariiGEN (Marys business/matter)
 Origin:
Latin: AlteriusGEN partisGEN periculum (Lit. Somewhere else danger The danger
  [coming] from somewhere else)
Greek (either concrete cities- or abstract locations families-): 裡虜略侶 畚
  凌僚溜虜凌 [Skr叩ts ho sfron鱈skou] (Lit. Socrates SofroniscoGEN
  Socrates, son of Sofronisco), 畆慮竜僚留溜僚 [Athen叩in] (Socrates from
  Athens).
Polish: haasNOM ulicyGEN noise of the street
 Quality (Only for individual level predicates, for stage level predicates ablative
  case is used):
Latin: Vir magnaeGEN auctoritatisGEN (Lit. Man of great authority)
Polish: czowiekNOM honoruGEN (a person/man of honour)
 Location through:
Greek: 慮劉凌留旅 竜隆溜凌旅凌 [th辿ousai ped鱈oioGEN] (Lit. Running
  meadowGEN Running through the meadow)
 Goal:
Sanskrit: PrjapaterGEN tmnam paridadmi (Lit. Prajapati myself
  give I give myself to Prajapati)
 Source:
Greek: 流 凌了 o畚 凌了 留劉竜旅 流 畆ハ竜旅 [h畍 pol箪s 炭 pol箪 ap辿khei
  t畍s h畍peiru] (Lit. The city not far away from the coast The city is
  not far away from the coast / departing from the coast)
Polish: mlekoNOM od krowyGEN (Lit. milk from the cow, cow milk)
 Part-whole: partitive Genitive
Latin: Magna pars ItaliaeGEN (A big part of Italy)
Greek: 竜凌 畚塾 留隆竜了畚塾 [p坦teros t畊n adelf畊nGEN] (Which of
  the brothers?)
Polish: butelkaNOM wodyGEN (a bottle of water)
 However, all uses locative establish a locative relation
  between nominals, either concrete or abstract: a
  nominal "belongs" to another in a concrete or abstract,
  metaphorical way. Belonging is a type of location
  (either central or terminal coincidence). Therefore, we
  propose to subsume all of these uses the "sphere of
  Dative".

 E.g.: Johns bag
  [V BE [P John [[WITH CENTRAL] bag]]
 Is English [s] a CL (Radeva-Bork, 2012) or a case mark?
  Abney (1987) supports the idea it is a CL in D0 raising to
  Spec-DP, but:

 It is not an argument, rather, a locative predicate
 It only appears within full DP nominals, not with
  pronouns, which inflect for Case:

i) A friend of [DP Johns]
ii) A friend of mine
iii) *A friend of [DP [[D mines] ]] (see Panagiotidis,
   2002 for an analysis of pronouns as D with empty root
   complements)
 There is, however, another type of "genitive: the
  "Subjective" and Objective", which appear in
  nominalizations as a light PP. These kinds of genitive
  also establish a locative relation between nominals: a
  conceptual event, syntactically categorized as a
  nominal, and a participant, either agent / initiator or
  theme. This conceptual relation must be syntactically
  realized without losing information (CP). This does
  not imply that there is a transformational relation
  between the nominalization and the tensed sentence
  form, but the explicature building process is
  analogous. These genitives are common features of
  Romance and Germanic languages, so they can not be
  considered an isolated anomaly.
Relational Semantic Structure
(Mateu, 2000; Jackendoff, 1987)
               T

      [event]       r

           Figure        r

                    P        Ground
E.g.: [T arrive [r Mary [r AT] the house]]
Possible Syntactic Realizations:
 non-transparent interface
      {time}                            {D}

  [time] {event}               [D]      {event}

      [event] {P}                    [event]   {P}

          {D}          {P}               {D}         {P}

                   P     {D}                   P       {D}


Mary arrived (at the house)    Mary卒s arrival (at the house)
Causative constructions
            R


   Italia       R

        [cause]       T

            [GO]             r

                  Albania        r

                    [WITH]       invasi坦n
Syntactic instantiations
         {D}                                                 {time}


 La         {cause}                                 [time]     {cause}


      {P}             {cause}                           {D}           {cause}

 P    Italia                                       D Italia
                [cause] {event}                                  [cause] {event}
                                                                   

                    {P}            {event}                                      {event}
                                                                  {D}

               de         {D}   [event] invasi坦n             D Albania [event] invasi坦n

                D Albania

More Related Content

Prepositions and Case Theory

  • 1. Diego Gabriel Krivochen (UNLP, Universit辰t Potsdam)
  • 2. Previous approaches Pesetsky & Torrego (2001, 2004, 2007) Vehicle Requirement on Merge (2007: 1): If 留 and 硫 merge, some feature F of 留 must probe F on 硫. Conditions for Probing: C-command Feature identity
  • 3. A model of Agree Agree (Feature sharing version) i) An unvalued feature F (a probe) on a head H at syntactic location 留 (F留) scans its c-command domain for another instance of F (a goal) at location 硫 (F硫) with which to agree. ii) Replace F留 with F硫, so that the same feature is present in both locations.
  • 4. Problems C-command is stipulatively defined upon 2-D tree-like representations. Restrictions on Merge: the operation does not follow from conceptual necessity but from intra-theoretical needs. Substantive complications: features, values, operations (Agree = Search + Copy Value)
  • 5. Case in P&Ts model Relation between Case in NPs and T finiteness (P&T, 2000: 5): The nature of nominative case Nominative case is uT on D. uT on D is valued by non-defective T The concept is extended to ACC case, depending on the T node that values the uninterpretable feature on D.
  • 6. Case as a subtype of Agree NOM = [TS [u-]DP[u-T]] ACC = [TO [u-] DP [u-T]]
  • 7. Case in Radical Minimalism Case is a configurational relation, not a substantive element (Cf. P&T, Chomsky) Relation between Theta-Theory and Case Theory: The optimal scenario would be that in which there is a univoque relation between theta positions and theta roles, and a Case interpretation for each theta-position.
  • 8. DeLancey (2001) () suppose we could demonstrate that there are, say, exactly x universal semantic roles which can occur as core arguments in a clause in human language. The most obvious language design would have x case markers, one for each underlying role; every argument would simply be marked for its semantic role, which could then be read directly off the surface morphosyntax () (our highlighting)
  • 9. vP 慮1 v [CAUSE] VP [GO/BE] PP 慮2 P [WITH] / [TO] 慮3
  • 10. Initiator will be assigned to the position 慮1, Theme (for Figure) and Location (for Ground) vary between 慮2 and 慮3 depending on the nature of the P head, central or terminal coincidence. If P is central, then the Ground will 慮2 and 慮3, Figure, while if P is terminal, it will be the other way around. Force is within the Initiator sphere Percept ("perceived entity") in the area of Theme Source, Path, Goal, Experiencer (see De Lancey, 2001), are interpreted within the Location sphere.
  • 11. Case is the result of the local relationship between an argument and a functional-procedural node. We will work with a system of three cases, also structured as "spheres", in close relation to thematic roles. These underlying and universal cases would be Nominative, Accusative and Dative, names that we maintain as a matter of convenience and expository purposes, but we really should talk about an Initiator Case (Agent / Force), a Theme Case and a Location Case (comprising variants of terminal / central coincidence), regardless possibilities of morphological realization in different languages. Nominative - Initiator Accusative - Theme Dative - Location
  • 12. Nominative: read off from a {Time, {D}} local relation, and interpreted thematically (in the explicature building process, see Sperber & Wilson, 2003) as Agent / Force Accusative: read off from a {Cause, {D}} local relation, and interpreted thematically as Theme, the object (Figure) located in / moving towards, etc. a Ground Dative: read off from a {P, {D}} local relation, and interpreted thematically as Location, the Ground in Talmys terms.
  • 13. An essential claim is that the spheres are not 束far apart損, but in interaction, and there are points of contact. There are elements, uses of the VI corresponding canonically to one 束Case損 that appear in unusual configurations: of these, we will say they are 束intersective uses損 of the Cases (blue circles): NOM ACC DAT
  • 14. Examples: Accusative > Dative: ACC expresses location in space, time or property (i, ii and iii), or goal in movement (iv). Direction Accusative: Latin: Eo RomamACC (Lit. Go Rome I go towards/to Rome) Sanskrit: grmamACC gacchami (Lit. Town go I go to the town) Polish: id na pocztACC I am going to the post office, id添 po niegoACC go for him (go to pick him up) Temporal Accusative: Latin: quamdiu, quamdudum, quanto tempore complements.
  • 15. ≒Double accusative in ditransitive constructions: traditionally referred to as thing ACC and person ACC, they are within the P domain, as Theme and Goal. Latin: Verres MilesiosACC navemACC poposcit. (Lit. Verres the milesians ship asked Verres asked a ship to the milesians), Quid meACC istudACC rogas? (Lit. Why to-me this ask? Why do you ask me this?) Greek: 隆旅隆略虜 凌 留樽隆留 流僚 粒留亮亮留旅虜流僚 [did叩sk to炭s pa樽dasACC t畍n grammatik畍nACC] (Lit. I teach to-the children grammar I teach grammar to the children) Sanskrit: rjnamACC vacanamACC abrav朝t (Lit. King some words said (He/She) said some words to the king)
  • 16. Accusative > Nominative: ACC is the overt subject in non-finite clauses. ECM (Exceptional Case Marking): Ingl辿s: I want [themACC to come] Lat鱈n: Video [teACC venire] (Lit. See you to-come, I see you coming) Griego: 了劉粒竜旅 竜 畆了慮竜樽僚 [l辿gei [seACC elthe樽nINF]] (Lit. dice te haber venido active aorist infinitive- (He/She) says you have come) Polish: Widz ciACC spicego. (I see you sleeping.) Dative > Nominative: Dative appears in subject position in the Spelled-Out form. Quirky case: Icelandic: HenniDAT leiddust 聾 NOM (Lit. Her bored they They bored her) eir MerDAT 聾 [MariaNOM vera garfu] (Lit. To me seems Mary be intelligent 坦tti Mary seems to me to be intelligent) Polish: MariiNOM znudzia si pracaNOM. (Mary got bored with work) JanowiDAT podoba si we Woszech. (John likes it in Italy.) Spanish: A JuanDAT leDAT basta con eso. (cf. Fernandez Soriano, 1999) A Mar鱈aDAT leDAT gusta el jazz
  • 17. Values of the Genitive (DAT Sphere) Posession (material or metaphorical): Sanskrit: Damayantys svaya畊baras (Lit. Damayantis choice) Latin: id est domusNOM regisGEN (Lit. This is house of the king This is the house of the king) Greek: 畆 凌畆偉採留 凌短 留 [h oik鱈a to短 patr坦sGEN] (Lit. The house of the father) Polish: sprawaNOM MariiGEN (Marys business/matter) Origin: Latin: AlteriusGEN partisGEN periculum (Lit. Somewhere else danger The danger [coming] from somewhere else) Greek (either concrete cities- or abstract locations families-): 裡虜略侶 畚 凌僚溜虜凌 [Skr叩ts ho sfron鱈skou] (Lit. Socrates SofroniscoGEN Socrates, son of Sofronisco), 畆慮竜僚留溜僚 [Athen叩in] (Socrates from Athens). Polish: haasNOM ulicyGEN noise of the street Quality (Only for individual level predicates, for stage level predicates ablative case is used): Latin: Vir magnaeGEN auctoritatisGEN (Lit. Man of great authority) Polish: czowiekNOM honoruGEN (a person/man of honour)
  • 18. Location through: Greek: 慮劉凌留旅 竜隆溜凌旅凌 [th辿ousai ped鱈oioGEN] (Lit. Running meadowGEN Running through the meadow) Goal: Sanskrit: PrjapaterGEN tmnam paridadmi (Lit. Prajapati myself give I give myself to Prajapati) Source: Greek: 流 凌了 o畚 凌了 留劉竜旅 流 畆ハ竜旅 [h畍 pol箪s 炭 pol箪 ap辿khei t畍s h畍peiru] (Lit. The city not far away from the coast The city is not far away from the coast / departing from the coast) Polish: mlekoNOM od krowyGEN (Lit. milk from the cow, cow milk) Part-whole: partitive Genitive Latin: Magna pars ItaliaeGEN (A big part of Italy) Greek: 竜凌 畚塾 留隆竜了畚塾 [p坦teros t畊n adelf畊nGEN] (Which of the brothers?) Polish: butelkaNOM wodyGEN (a bottle of water)
  • 19. However, all uses locative establish a locative relation between nominals, either concrete or abstract: a nominal "belongs" to another in a concrete or abstract, metaphorical way. Belonging is a type of location (either central or terminal coincidence). Therefore, we propose to subsume all of these uses the "sphere of Dative". E.g.: Johns bag [V BE [P John [[WITH CENTRAL] bag]]
  • 20. Is English [s] a CL (Radeva-Bork, 2012) or a case mark? Abney (1987) supports the idea it is a CL in D0 raising to Spec-DP, but: It is not an argument, rather, a locative predicate It only appears within full DP nominals, not with pronouns, which inflect for Case: i) A friend of [DP Johns] ii) A friend of mine iii) *A friend of [DP [[D mines] ]] (see Panagiotidis, 2002 for an analysis of pronouns as D with empty root complements)
  • 21. There is, however, another type of "genitive: the "Subjective" and Objective", which appear in nominalizations as a light PP. These kinds of genitive also establish a locative relation between nominals: a conceptual event, syntactically categorized as a nominal, and a participant, either agent / initiator or theme. This conceptual relation must be syntactically realized without losing information (CP). This does not imply that there is a transformational relation between the nominalization and the tensed sentence form, but the explicature building process is analogous. These genitives are common features of Romance and Germanic languages, so they can not be considered an isolated anomaly.
  • 22. Relational Semantic Structure (Mateu, 2000; Jackendoff, 1987) T [event] r Figure r P Ground E.g.: [T arrive [r Mary [r AT] the house]]
  • 23. Possible Syntactic Realizations: non-transparent interface {time} {D} [time] {event} [D] {event} [event] {P} [event] {P} {D} {P} {D} {P} P {D} P {D} Mary arrived (at the house) Mary卒s arrival (at the house)
  • 24. Causative constructions R Italia R [cause] T [GO] r Albania r [WITH] invasi坦n
  • 25. Syntactic instantiations {D} {time} La {cause} [time] {cause} {P} {cause} {D} {cause} P Italia D Italia [cause] {event} [cause] {event} {P} {event} {event} {D} de {D} [event] invasi坦n D Albania [event] invasi坦n D Albania